Please enable JavaScript.
Coggle requires JavaScript to display documents.
Ethics (Stroud: (2. Three ways extreme moral demands come about (in…
Ethics
Singer:
1. Intro: Famine, Affluence, and Morality - 1972: CTA - our moral conceptual scheme needs to be altered and with it the way of life that has come to be taken for granted in our societies.
Acknowledges that moral norms within societies have developed so as to help those societies function as well as possible rather than for other reasons. He says this may explain moral societal norms but doesn’t justify them.
He maintains that “ when all considerations of this sort have been taken into account, the conclusion remains: we ought to be preventing as much suffering as we can without sacrificing something else of comparable moral importance.”
2. Strong Version: If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening without sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance we ought morally to do it until we reach a point of diminishing marginal utility.
By comparable moral importance he means: He admits the fact that his notion of comparable moral importance & moral significance is vague. Roughly it means the following:
- Causing anything else comparably bad to happen
- Doing something that is wrong in itself
- Failing to promote some moral good comparable in significance to the bad thing that we can prevent
“ I can see no good reason for holding the moderate version of the principle rather than the strong version.”
3. Weak version: If it is in our power to prevent something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything morally significant, we ought morally to do it.
Why the adherence to what sounds like a relatively simple and reasonable principle would result in such drastic societal and personal change:
-
Charity would become duty and duty alone would become immorality. Reduction in what was once considered supergatory.
Garrett Cullity::
Consequentialism-Only-Worry: Singer’s conclusions only follow from consequentialist assumptions which contradicts his claim that his argument should be acceptable to consequentialists and non-consequentialists. However Cullity wants to put forth a version of Singer's argument which does not require that one be consequentialist in order to embrace it.
-
-
-
Reading is "International Aid and the Scope of Kindness" : Very importantly here what Cullity is doing is not actually arguing against Singer's conclusion he is just formulating an alternative argument so that it can be accepted by those who pose the three objections outlined below.
His Reformulation of Singer's Argument: Basically holds that affluent people not donating to a cause they could is unkind and unjust so long as there are no countervailing considerations and that the fact that affluent people are not immediately presented with a threat is not a countervailing consideration so any person that does not donate is unkind and unjust and therefore morally wrong. -- His new argument thus revolves around a reformulation of kindness and justice so as to dodge the three objections which he highlights.
His goal with this has been to make sense of a moral error without resorting to a moral theory so as to be able to counter the practical ethicists reply.
The way he does this is by holding that the practical ethicist justifies ethical practice with certain virtuous concerns, not just doing what is a well-entrenched practice.
From here then he can hold that kindness and justice/fairness inform the need to pull the kid out of the pond and thus to donate to aid agencies is unjust and unfair and from here is the reformulation of his argument.
Cullity & Demandingness: Where does he end up finding that the conclusion is too demanding? One thing he has is the countervailing condition so that when aid-donating reaches a certain point one must not donate past that because doing so counts as a countervailing condition.
However the issue is that this point of countervailing conditions may only be reached when the cost to me of not donating further money to aid is the same as the cost to me of justifying me not saving a child from drowning right in front of me.
Can one just reply that the non-immediacy of a threat (ie. it being in the third world and far away from us) not be enough to count as a countervailing consideration and then let us get away with it?
Stroud:
She is bringing forth "they can't take that away from me" arguments which are essentially arguments about demandingness.
-
1. Williams:
Ground Projects: Refers to certain kinds of projects as "ground projects". These are sets of projects that are closely related to ones existence and which give meaning to one's life and a utilitarian argument cannot force one to give that up.
(B) Utility Network Inapplicability: "it's absurd to demand of a man when the sums come in from the utility network that he should just step aside from his own projects"
Part of his reasoning is that utilitarianism treats "my" ground projects simply as "someones" ground projects and thus diminishes the real value they hold for me.
(A) Frau Paul: She provides the frau paul case which shows that sometimes it is not wrong to give up ground projects.
From here she holds that the reasons one should not give up their ground projects are not moral reasons and are exogenous to morality.
-
Violette Igneski:
3. MISC:
Colin McGinn: She cites an interesting response from Colin McGinn which is that the threshold for sacrifice is set at a point where something is meaningful to us rather than others.
McGinn's Principle: "We should help out the distant poor when and only when their need is desperate and we will not sacrifice anything in our own life that is meaningful to us."
An uncharitable interpretation would see this as basically just saying that we actually have no real obligation to help the poor or needy at all.
Agent themself determines what is meaningful and what adds value to their life and thus also where the limits lie
This seems much more reasonable and is also kind of what is actually done. Then the more an individual agent includes the benefit of others within what is meaningful to them and thus the further they push out the limits of their morality and concern for others the more a moral person they are to be considered.
This is what actually kind of happens in reality too.
-
Murphy's Argument: Beneficience is a cooperative project and we must each do our fair share. Our fair share is determined on the assumption of fully compliance and does not change if there is only partial compliance.
1. Intro: She holds that morality is about more than maximising good states of affairs and she does not deny that we should care about happiness but this does not entail an obligation to make people as happy as possible.
She kind of offers a reformulation of how we should think about all of this: She says that our job is to provide people with their basic needs but also to live out our lives which is what is valuable about agency in the first place.
This actually links back to Cullity's beneficience argument a bit in that it holds that the reason for beneficience is to provide others with the space needed to live out their lives but if we sacrificie this space in order to pursue beneficien the whole point of the B in the first place is being given up by us for others.
-
Stephen White:
Responsibility: ("Responsibility and the Demands of Morality") - It is essentially just what one is answerable for. It is being eligible for moral responses (eg. positive or negative appraisal, reactive attitudes to behavioral expressions).
-
Utilitarianism imposes upon agents a kind of responsibility we can call negative answerability which holds a person negatively answerable for conduct insofar as she is answerable for what she does not do.
The limits of what we are demanded to do can in a sense be set by the fact that a person's answerability for their own well-being is more extensive than what she may appropriately be held to answer for when it comes to the lives of others.
-